The subtitle of this book (Aesthetics in the Work of Guðbergur
Bergsson) is a curious one. I say this because I think that Barnett Newman was
right when he observed that, “Aesthetics is for the artist as ornithology is for the
birds.” I take it that Newman meant that, just as the studies of ornithologists have
no
effect on how birds go about their lives, so the cogitations of aestheticians have
no
effect on how artists practice their craft. Artists are in the business of creating
works
with aesthetic value. Their works do not present an account of aesthetic value. Such
accounts come later and are the work of aestheticians. Works of art can, however,
address
moral and existential questions on which philosophers have reflected. Artworks can
also be
shaped by the social context in which they originate. Attitudes and mores of a society
can
be manifested in a work of art. This is the view (despite the subtitle of her book)
that
Bjarnadóttir defends. References to aesthetics are mainly superfluous.
Bjarnadóttir holds that Bergsson’s “dialogue with poets, novelists, and philosophers
who are prominent within the history
of ideas and world literature” have shaped Bergsson’s work (154). She discusses,
in particular, the significance of Augustine, Blanchot, Kierkegaard,
Nietzsche and Plotinus. While various poets, novelists and philosophers have undoubtedly
affected Bergsson’s writing, Bjarnadóttir does not provide a convincing account of
how the
philosophers she discusses illuminate Bergsson’s work. At the same time, Bjarnadóttir
holds that, “in Bergsson’s writings, the reality of Icelandic culture and society
is interwoven
with
elements of the literature and history of ideas of the West” (182). Her discussion
of Bergsson’s relationship to Icelandic culture is more successful
than her discussion of philosophical influences.
One might wonder how Bjarnadóttir selected the figures she chooses to discuss in relation
to Bergsson. Augustine, Blanchot, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Plotinus are a pretty
heterogeneous collection of philosophers and one might expect to find that what they
have
in common is their importance for Bergsson. The Preface to Bjarnadóttir’s book reveals
otherwise. What they have in common is that Bjarnadóttir read them in the course of
her
graduate studies. While in graduate school she took courses on Blanchot, Kierkegaard
and
Nietzsche. At about the same time she read Hannah Arendt’s book on St. Augustine.
I am not
quite sure how Plotinus ended up in the book. His connection to Bergsson is tenuous.
Bjarnadóttir is aware that the connection between Bergsson and Plotinus seems sketchy.
She writes that, “one might suppose that the ideas of Plotinus concerning beauty and
existence are
altogether irrelevant to contemporary discussions on the subject” (92). One might
indeed. Even if Plotinus exercises a residual influence on contemporary
thought about beauty, Bjarnadóttir does little to convince the reader that the
neo-Platonist has particular significance for Bergsson’s thought about beauty. Bergsson
wrote an essay (helpfully included as an appendix in this volume) entitled “Ideas
of Beauty” and Bjarnadóttir holds that the search for beauty is a
theme running through his work. She does not, however, provide a convincing case for
thinking that Bergsson’s conception of beauty in any way resembles or is influenced
by
that of Plotinus. She advances two reasons for thinking that Bergsson and Plotinus
have
something in common: it “seems that the aesthetics of Bergsson’s works emerges from
concerns that relate to
both
life and art. It is also a response to how the relationship between humanity and beauty
have been considered in the past” (103). This could be said about pretty much everyone
who has written about beauty and this
does not establish that reflection on Plotinus casts light on Bergsson.
The relevance of Augustine to Bergsson is only marginally greater than the relevance
of
Plotinus. Perhaps the closest connection that Bjarnadóttir can find is that, in The Mouse that Skulks, “Bergsson attempts to describe the human condition from a Christian perspective”
(86–87). Suppose that this is true. It would still be unclear why Augustine, as opposed
to
any other Christian thinker, is relevant to Bergsson’s writings. Other similarities
between Bergsson and Augustine seem comparably slight. Augustine wrote an autobiography.
Bergsson’s novels sometimes take the form of fictional autobiographies. Even if this
similarity were striking, many people besides Augustine have written autobiographies.
In
the absence of any evidence that Augustine exerted some influence on Bergsson (and
Bjarnadóttir provides little) it is hard to see how the author of the Confessions helps us understand the author of The Mouse that
Skulks.
While there are some superficial parallels between Bergsson and Augustine, there are
conspicuous dissimilarities. One obvious difference between Augustine and Bergsson
is
that, “while Augustine turns to God, the narrator of The Mouse that
Skulks turns to the world and all its material things” (87). In general, Bergsson seems
to be a post-Christian writer. The differences between
Bergsson and Augustine are, it seems, more salient than any similarities. I was left
unconvinced that Bergsson’s writing displays the influence of any of Augustine’s thought,
aesthetic or otherwise.
Let us turn now to a consideration of how the aesthetics of Blanchot are present in
Bergsson’s writings. Blanchot is best known for anticipating postmodern or
poststructuralist literary theory. One way to characterize his view is to say that
(like subsequent French theorists) Blanchot is a sceptic about meaning: works of
literature do not have a determinate or determinable meaning. (One might wonder why
Blanchot is considered rather than other postmodernists. That question is answered
in the
Preface.) Bjarnadóttir also regards Blanchot as an existentialist. So the question
is
whether postmodern and existentialist themes, of the sort found in Blanchot, are echoed
in
Bergsson.
Bjarnadóttir does not provide a compelling case for answering this question in the
affirmative. She interprets Blanchot as saying that, “the ‘impossibility of literature’
… makes for its very possibility.” She then holds that this “idea is not foreign to
Guðbergur Bergsson” since he repeatedly “expresses the idea of the unfinished nature of art and the
potentialities that reside in a work that is not
‘complete’” (30). Bergsson might, in expressing this idea, express something like
Blanchot’s view
of
literature, but it is not obvious that he does. (The suggestion Bergsson’s writings
express anything at all is at odds with scepticism about meaning. But this paradox
haunts
all postmodernism.) Other attempts to find parallels between Blanchot and Bergsson
are
equally speculative. Bjarnadóttir finds evidence of Blanchot’s existentialism in these
lines: “I have lost life / the night has come and offered me wakefulness” (30). Well,
maybe, but for a start, Blanchot is not a paradigmatic existentialist. Why
not choose another existentialist? (For what it is worth, Blanchot is not on Wikipedia’s
list of prominent existentialists.) Secondly, not every gloomy poem is a manifestation
of
existentialism.
Bjarnadóttir is no more successful in showing that Kierkegaard’s existentialism is
manifested in Bergsson’s writings. As Bjarnadóttir notes, Kierkegaard maintained “that
he never wrote about anything other than the difficulty of being a Christian
in
dialogue with the terrible deception: Christendom” (120). A similar claim cannot plausibly
be made (Bjarnadóttir does not make it) about
Bergsson. Some superficial similarities between Bergsson and Kierkegaard can be found,
and
Bjarnadóttir finds them. For example, like Kierkegaard, Bergsson is concerned with
faith.
But even Bjarnadóttir has to admit that it is faith of a different sort (151).
Nietzsche is the final philosopher whose relationship to Bergsson is considered in
some
detail. Unlike the other philosophers Bjarnadóttir discusses, Nietzsche is known to
have
been read by and to have influenced Bergsson. Whether we find an important influence
of
Nietzsche’s thought on Bergsson’s writing is another matter. The Birth of
Tragedy is the principal source of Nietzsche’s aesthetics considered here, but the
single most important idea in this book receives very little attention. This is
Nietzsche’s belief that the most valuable sort of art combines elements of Apollonian
and
Dionysian art. This art most effectively shields us from the horror of reality. I
do not
see much evidence that Bergsson conceived of his art as intended to shield us from
reality
by blending the Apollonian and the Dionysian. On the contrary, Bjarnadóttir’s book
gives
the overall impression of an author who gazes unblinkingly at modern life. It is not
even
clear that Bergsson’s writing could be a candidate for tragic art, in Nietzsche’s
sense of
the term. The full title of Nietzsche’s book provides a clue to the sort of art that
concerned him: The Birth of Tragedy from the Spirit of Music.
Nietzsche believed that such art is found in Attic tragedy. For a time he believed
that it
is also found in Wagner’s operas. That is, he believed that music drama combines
Apollonian and Dionysian elements.
The remainder of Bjarnadóttir’s book is devoted to an examination of the Icelandic
background to Bergsson’s writing. One chapter provides a survey of Icelandic writing
on
aesthetics since the nineteenth century. The views canvassed seem mainly to contrast
with
views expressed by Bergsson. Another chapter is devoted to the contemporary Icelandic
context of Bergsson’s writings. This chapter includes a review of some of the early
reception of Bergsson’s work. This chapter does not have much to do with the role
of
aesthetic or philosophical thought in Bergsson’s writings.
Augustine, Plotinus, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Blanchot are a diverse set of
philosophers with inconsistent views. This alone makes it unlikely that the thought
of
these writers would be simultaneously manifested in the fiction of a single writer.
In any
case, Bjarnadóttir does not succeed in showing that the aesthetic or other philosophical
thought of these thinkers is present in a significant way in the work of Guðbergur
Bergsson.
James O. Young